Quine dies at 92

From: Francisco Yus Ramos (F.YUS@mail.ono.es)
Date: Fri Dec 29 2000 - 15:24:23 GMT

  • Next message: Deirdre Wilson: "CONFERENCE ON RECENT PERSPECTIVES ON DISCOURSE"

            The New York Times
            December 29, 2000, Arts

            W. V. Quine, Philosopher Who Analyzed
            Language and Reality, Dies at 92

            By CHRISTOPHER LEHMANN-HAUPT

                  W. V. Quine, a logician and Harvard philosophy professor
    whose
                  analysis of language and its relation to reality made him
    one of
            the most influential philosophers of the 20th century, died on
    Monday at
            a hospital in Boston, where he lived. He was 92.

            As a mathematical logician who wrote and published prolifically,
    Mr.
            Quine was often perceived as a philosopher who focused his
    analytic
            talents on many apparently disparate doctrines and theses. Yet
    those
            who understood him best insisted on his status as a system
    builder, or a
            thinker who addressed and attempted to answer the larger
    questions of
            philosophy.

            Stuart Hampshire, a fellow philosopher, called him in 1971 "our
    most
            distinguished living systematic philosopher."

            Like most philosophers, Mr. Quine set out to define the reality
    of the
            world and how humans fit into that reality. He concluded that a
    person
            can only understand the world empirically, or through direct
    experience
            of it. In "The Philosophy of W. V. Quine: An Expository Essay,"
    a study
            that the subject endorsed, Roger F. Gibson Jr. wrote that if Mr.
    Quine's
            project could be summed up in a single sentence, that sentence
    would
            read, "Quine's philosophy is a systematic attempt to answer,
    from a
            uniquely empiricistic point of view, what he takes to be the
    central
            question of epistemology, namely, `How do we acquire our theory
    of the
            world?' "

            Mr. Quine's answer, in a nutshell, began by rephrasing the
    question to
            read, "How do we acquire our talk about the world?" In his
    radically
            empiricist view, nothing that humans know about the world lies
    outside
            the realm of language, and so he insisted that any theory of
    knowledge
            depended on a theory of language, which he duly set about
    developing
            and which became the framework of his philosophy.

            In pursuing this objective Mr. Quine found himself in a distinct
    position
            among his contemporaries. Among 20th-century philosophers were
    the
            so-called historicists  those willing to speculate about and
    proclaim
            metaphysical truths independent of empirical evidence  and the
            formalists  those mathematical logicians who considered
    philosophy an
            autonomous, ahistorical discipline that replaced metaphysical
    speculation
            with scientific thinking. In the battle between followers of
    those views,
            Mr. Quine was a standard-bearer in the latter camp, a hero of
    empiricism
            who once declared that "philosophy of science is philosophy
    enough."

            Changing Direction

            In a Scholarly Battle

            This led him to fight in the ranks of the so- called logical
    positivists, or
            those like his European friends A. J. Ayer and Rudolf Carnap,
    who
            asserted that all statements of truth must be based on
    observable data.
            He even helped to shift the main ground of their battle from
    Europe to the
            United States. Yet Mr. Quine later challenged them in what is
    arguably
            the best known of his many published essays, "Two Dogmas of
            Empiricism." It first appeared in the Philosophical Review in
    January
            1951 and was reprinted in 1953 in a collection of his essays
    titled "From
            a Logical Point of View."

            The essay set out to undermine the two main points of
    positivism. First,
            Mr. Quine rejected the fundamental distinction between what Kant
    had
            called analytic and synthetic propositions, or the distinction
    between
            statements that seem true no matter what (like "all bachelors
    are
            unmarried") and those that are true because of the way things
    happen to
            be (like "Mr. X is a bachelor"). (This position, incidentally,
    earned him a
            place in Dan Dennett's "Philosophers' Lexicon," in which names
    of
            philosophers are construed as verbs or common nouns: to "quine"
    is to
            repudiate a clear distinction.)

            To deny the distinction between analytic and synthetic
    statements meant
            that nothing could be known independent of experience.

            Second, the essay argued against what he called the dogma of
            reductionism, or "the belief," as he put it, "that each
    meaningful statement
            is equivalent to some logical construct upon terms which refer
    to
            immediate experience." In other words, nothing in a person's
    experience
            lies beyond meaningful statement about it.

            Although this seemed to amount to a rejection of all knowledge
    of a
            reality beyond our senses, Mr. Quine did not completely shut the
    door to
            a world out there. The alternative that he preferred was this
    explanation:
            "The totality of our so-called knowledge or beliefs, from the
    most casual
            matters of geography and history to the profoundest laws of
    atomic
            physics or even of pure mathematics and logic, is a man-made
    fabric
            which impinges on experience only along the edges."

            This position led him to two more conclusions about the nature
    of
            meaning and what humans can know about objective reality. One,
            enunciated in his 1960 book, "Word and Object," was that when
            translating from one language to another, or even from one
    sentence to
            another within the same language, there were bound to be many
            contradictory ways to understand the meaning and that there was
    no
            sense in asking which of them was right.

            This works, in his view, with what he called ontological
    relativity, which
            holds that because our theories of what exists are not
    sufficiently
            determined by the experiences that give rise to them, quite
    different
            accounts of what there is, each with its own interpretation of
    the
            evidence, may be equally in accord with that evidence.

            To the objection that surely at least physical objects must
    figure in all
            theories of what is out there, Mr. Quine responded, yes, in
    practice,
            although he said he considered physical objects a matter of
    convenience.

            Tools for Determining

            The Real World

            "As an empiricist," he wrote toward the end of "Two Dogmas of
            Empiricism," "I continue to think of the conceptual scheme of
    science as a
            tool, ultimately, for predicting future experience in the light
    of past
            experience. Physical objects are conceptually imported into the
    situation
            as convenient intermediaries not by definition in terms of
    experience, but
            simply as irreducible posits comparable, epistemologically, to
    the gods of
            Homer."

            He concluded: "For my part I do, qua lay physicist, believe in
    physical
            objects and not in Homer's gods; and I consider it a scientific
    error to
            believe otherwise. But in point of epistemological footing, the
    physical
            objects and the gods differ only in degree and not in kind. Both
    sorts of
            entities enter our conceptions only as cultural posits."

            Willard Van Orman Quine, or Van to his friends, was born on June
    25,
            1908, in Akron, Ohio, the second son of Cloyd Robert Quine, a
            machinist and successful businessman, and Harriet (Van Orman)
    Quine.
            The surname is from the Celtic language Manx, Mr. Quine's
    paternal
            grandfather having emigrated from the Isle of Man to Akron. Mr.
    Quine
            was named Willard after his mother's brother, a mathematician.

            The nominal connection seemed to work. He took a liking to
            mathematics in high school and majored in it at Oberlin,
    although
            philology and philosophy also interested him early. (During his
    junior year
            at college his mother presented him with Whitehead and Russell's

            "Principia Mathematica" and Skeat's Etymological Dictionary, the
    latter
            of which, he said, "I persistently consulted and explored over
    the
            succeeding half century," a fact attested to by the liveliness
    and clarity of
            his writing.)

            About his subsequent teaching career he said: "What I enjoyed
    most was
            more the mathematical end than the philosophical, because of it
    being less
            a matter of opinion. Clarifying, not defending. Resting on
    proof."

            His honors thesis at Oberlin used the system of "Principia
    Mathematica"
            to prove with 18 pages of symbols a law having to do with ways
    of
            combining logical classes. (He later edited the 18 pages down to
    three
            for the Journal of the London Mathematical Society.) His thesis
    landed
            him at Harvard University, where he switched to philosophy to
    study with
            Alfred North Whitehead. ("He radiated greatness and seemed old
    as the
            hills," Mr. Quine wrote in his autobiography, "The Time of My
    Life." "I
            retained a vivid sense of being in the presence of the great.")

            Trying to Grasp

            The Nature of Science

            Only two years later, in 1932, he had earned his Ph.D., his
    dissertation
            being an attempt, in his words, "like `Principia,' to comprehend
    the
            foundations of logic and mathematics and hence of the abstract
    nature of
            all science." (It was published in revised form by the Harvard
    University
            Press with the title "A System of Logistic.")

            He then went to Europe on a Sheldon Traveling Fellowship and
    spent the
            next year in Vienna, Prague and Warsaw, where he studied,
    lectured and
            met various members of the Vienna Circle of logical positivists,
    among
            them Philip Frank, Moritz Schlick, Alfred Tarski, A. J. Ayer,
    their
            English spokesman, Kurt Gvdel (who preferred not to be called a
    logical
            positivist), and Rudolf Carnap, from whom, Mr. Quine said, "I
    gained
            more . . . than from any other philosopher." (In Vienna he
    dropped a
            note to Wittgenstein, who never responded.)

            The European interlude allowed him to indulge his lifelong
    passion for
            crossing borders (perhaps related to his penchant for denying
            distinctions, or, more likely, inspired by a youthful ardor for
    philately),
            which, according to a count he made late in his life, was to
    take him into
            118 countries, over another 19, and within sight of 8 more,
    among the
            last being China, Oman and Bangladesh. His autobiography
    describes
            many of these visits somewhat matter-of-factly. His early love
    of
            geography was also reflected in a gift for drawing maps, which
    later
            extended to sketching portraits, several of which appear in his
            autobiography.

            In 1933 he returned to Harvard as a junior fellow in the newly
    formed
            Society of Fellows, which meant three years of unfettered
    research.
            Another junior fellow that year was the psychologist B. F.
    Skinner, with
            whom Mr. Quine came to share, as he put it, "the fundamental
    position
            that an explanation  not the deepest one, but one of a
    shallower kind
             is possible at the purest behavioral level."

            In 1936 Mr. Quine became an instructor in philosophy at Harvard,

            where he taught, off and on, for the rest of his life,
    interrupted only by
            service in the Navy during World War II, when he did
    cryptanalytic
            work translating the German submarine cypher in Washington, as
    well as
            by his globe-girdling travels, the bestowal of medals, prizes
    and some
            dozen-and-a-half honorary degrees, and by lectures and classes
            delivered all over the world.

            A Harvard Professor

            To Notable Students

            His students at Harvard included Donald Davidson and Burton
    Dreben,
            the philosophers; Tom Lehrer, the mathematician and songwriter;
    and
            Theodore J. Kaczynski, the Unabomber ("although I don't remember

            him," Mr. Quine told an interviewer, "he tied for top, 98.9
    percent").

            In the Navy he met Marjorie Boynton, a Wave in his office who
    became
            his second wife in 1948. His first marriage to Naomi Clayton in
    1930
            ended in divorce in 1947. His second wife died in 1998. He is
    survived
            by two daughters from his first marriage, Elizabeth Quine
    Roberts and
            Norma Quine; a son and daughter from his second, Douglas Boynton

            Quine and Margaret Quine McGovern; five grandchildren; and a
            great-grandson.

            A Positive View

            Of State Lotteries

            Mr. Quine published about 20 books, some reprinted in multiple
    editions
            and several translated into as many as eight languages. One of
    the more
            accessible works, "Quiddities: An Intermittently Philosophical
    Dictionary"
            (1987), was praised in The New York Times by John Gross in
    general
            for "a deadpan humor that can light up even the most austere
    subjects"
            and in particular for commending the state lottery as " `a
    public subsidy of
            intelligence,' on the grounds that `it yields public income that
    is calculated
            to lighten the tax burden of us prudent abstainers at the
    expense of the
            benighted masses of wishful thinkers.' "

            At the end of "The Time of My Life," Mr. Quine wrote: "I am
    orderly and
            I am frugal. For the most part my only emotion is impatience,"
    he
            continued. "I am deeply moved by occasional passages of poetry,
    and
            so, characteristically, I read little of it."

            Although a "Quine" is defined in the New Hackers Dictionary as
    "a
            program that generates a copy of its own source text as its
    complete
            output," Mr. Quine never wrote on a computer, always preferring
    the
            1927 Remington typewriter that he first used for his doctoral
    thesis.
            Because that project contained so many special symbols, he had
    to have
            the machine adjusted by removing the second period, the second
    comma
            and the question mark.

            "You don't miss the question mark?" a reporter once asked him.

            "Well, you see," he replied, "I deal in certainties."



    This archive was generated by hypermail 2b29 : Fri Dec 29 2000 - 15:28:14 GMT