BOUNCE relevance@ling.ucl.ac.uk: Non-member submission from [Dan Sperber <dan@sperber.com>]

From: robyn carston (robyn@linguistics.ucl.ac.uk)
Date: Mon Aug 28 2000 - 14:56:46 GMT

  • Next message: Dan Sperber: "new book on metarepresentations"

    >Date: Mon, 28 Aug 2000 15:02:04 +0100 (BST)
    >From: owner-relevance@linguistics.ucl.ac.uk
    >To: relevance-approval@linguistics.ucl.ac.uk
    >Subject: BOUNCE relevance@ling.ucl.ac.uk: Non-member submission from
    [Dan Sperber <dan@sperber.com>]
    >
    >>From dan@sperber.com Mon Aug 28 15:01:58 2000
    >Return-Path: <dan@sperber.com>
    >Received: from mail-f.bcc.ac.uk by crow.phon.ucl.ac.uk (8.8.8+Sun/SMI-SVR4)
    > id PAA03332; Mon, 28 Aug 2000 15:01:57 +0100 (BST)
    >Received: from front2.grolier.fr by mail-f.bcc.ac.uk with SMTP (PP) with
    ESMTP;
    > Mon, 28 Aug 2000 15:01:29 +0100
    >Received: from l4c7i8.poly.polytechnique.fr
    (bas1-154.idf3-1.club-internet.fr [195.36.247.154]) by front2.grolier.fr
    (8.9.3/No_Relay+No_Spam_MGC990224)
    > with ESMTP id QAA10101 for <relevance@linguistics.ucl.ac.uk>;
    > Mon, 28 Aug 2000 16:01:24 +0200 (MET DST)
    >Message-Id: <4.3.2.7.2.20000828155031.00b14d60@pop3.club-internet.fr>
    >X-Sender: sperber@pop3.club-internet.fr
    >X-Mailer: QUALCOMM Windows Eudora Version 4.3.2
    >Date: Mon, 28 Aug 2000 15:52:18 +0200
    >To: relevance@linguistics.ucl.ac.uk
    >From: Dan Sperber <dan@sperber.com>
    >Subject: New book on metarepresentations
    >Mime-Version: 1.0
    >Content-Type: text/plain; charset="iso-8859-1"; format=flowed
    >Content-Transfer-Encoding: quoted-printable
    >Content-Length: 13423
    >
    >Just out:
    >
    >Dan Sperber (ed.)
    >METAREPRESENTATIONS: A MULTIDISCIPLINARY PERSPECTIVE
    >(Vancouver Studies in Cognitive Science 10)
    >Oxford University Press USA, July 2000 (cloth 0195141148, paper 0195141156)
    >
    >Cognitive systems are characterized by their ability to construct and=20
    >process mental representations. Cognitive systems capable of communicating=
    >=20
    >also produce and interpret public representations. Representations, whether=
    >=20
    >mental or public, are themselves objects in the world; they are found=20
    >inside cognizers and in the vicinity of communicators; they are potential=20
    >objects of second order representations or "metarepresentations". While the=
    >=20
    >term "metarepresentation" gained currency only in the late 80's, the=20
    >general idea is much older. Under a variety of other names, philosophers,=20
    >psychologists, linguists, logicians, semioticians, literary theorists,=20
    >theologians, and anthropologists have been interested in different types of=
    >=20
    >metarepresentations. Notwithstanding historical antecedents, much recent=20
    >work on metarepresentations is truly novel as a result of being pursued=20
    >within the framework of evolutionary and cognitive psychology, and of=20
    >modern philosophy of language and mind. This collection of essays reflects=
    >=20
    >these new developments. It is organized in three parts:
    >
    >PART I: The evolution of metarepresentation
    >PART II: Metarepresentations in mind
    >PART III: Metarepresentations, language, and meaning
    >
    >Here is a brief guide to the contents of the volume:
    >
    >PART I: The evolution of metarepresentation
    >
    >In "Making Tools for Thinking," DANIEL DENNETT raises fundamental=20
    >challenges. The notion of a metarepresentation cannot be clearer than that=
    >=20
    >of a representation. The notion of a representation can be understood in a=
    >=20
    >variety of senses, some shallower and wider, such that we would be willing=
    >=20
    >to attribute representations to simpler animals and devices. Others senses=
    >=20
    >are narrower and richer, such that we might be tempted to think of=20
    >representation as specifically humans. Do these richer senses of=20
    >"representation" somehow presuppose that representations are being (or are=
    >=20
    >capable of being) metarepresented? Can we conceive of the emergence in=20
    >evolution and in cognitive development of metarepresentations - and of the=
    >=20
    >type of representations that requires metarepresentation - in a purely=20
    >mind-internal way or should we see this emergence as linked to the=20
    >availability in the environment of representational tools - linguistic=20
    >symbols for instance - there to be metarepresented? These issues are well=20
    >worth keeping in mind when reading the rest of the book
    >
    >In "The Mind beyond itself," ROBERT WILSON speculates on issues similar to=
    >=20
    >those raised by Dennett. He criticizes the individualistic approach to=20
    >cognition and develops the idea that that many higher cognitive functions,=
    >=20
    >and in particular metarepresentational capacities, are essentially=20
    >world-involving. He discusses the cases of memory, theory-of-mind, and=20
    >cultural evolution, and argues that, in each case, external symbols and=20
    >their metarepresentations play an essential role.
    >
    >In "Consider the source: The evolution of adaptations for decoupling and=20
    >metarepresentations," LEDA COSMIDES AND JOHN TOOBY outline a novel and=20
    >wide-ranging approach to the evolution of metarepresentational abilities.=20
    >They start from the observation that human evolution is characterized by a=
    >=20
    >dramatic increase in the use of contingent information for the regulation=20
    >of improvised behavior tailored to local conditions. They argue that=20
    >adaptations evolved to solve the problems posed by using local and=20
    >contingent information include a specialized "scope syntax," decoupling=20
    >systems, and a variety of metarepresentational devices. These adaptations=20
    >are essential to planning, communication, mindreading, pretence, deception,=
    >=20
    >inference about past or hidden causal relations, mental simulation, and=20
    >much else. Thus Cosmides and Tooby view mindreading as only one of the=20
    >functions that has driven the evolution of metarepresentational abilities=20
    >and of human intelligence in general. One may note that the=20
    >representational powers they see as having evolved in the human mind are=20
    >interestingly similar to those Fran=E7ois Recanati analyzes from a semantic=
    >=20
    >point of view in his chapter.
    >
    >In "Metarepresentations in an evolutionary perspective," DAN SPERBER=20
    >envisage the possibility that humans might be endowed, not with one, but=20
    >with several evolved metarepresentational abilities. He argues that, beside=
    >=20
    >the standard metapsychological mindreading ability, humans might have a=20
    >comprehension module aimed at the online interpretation of utterances, and=
    >=20
    >a logico-argumentative module, aimed at persuading others and avoiding=20
    >deception.
    >
    >In "Chimpanzee cognition and the question of mental re-representation",=20
    >ANDREW WHITEN examines the state of the evidence regarding the ability of=20
    >chimpanzees to engage in imitation, mindreading, and pretence. He argues=20
    >that chimpanzees have a capacity for a most basic form of=20
    >metarepresentation, which he calls "re-representation" and which are mental=
    >=20
    >representations whose content derives from other mental representations=20
    >either in oneself or in others. He discusses how these abilities in apes=20
    >relate to the different "grades" of metarepresentation envisaged in the=20
    >theory-of-mind literature, in particular by Leslie and Perner. This chapter=
    >=20
    >provides a welcome transition to the second part.
    >
    >PART II: Metarepresentations in mind
    >
    >In "The mentalizing folk," ALVIN GOLDMAN raises central questions regarding=
    >=20
    >people's abilities to metarepresent mental representations. What concepts=20
    >of mental states do people possess? How do they attribute specific=20
    >instances of mental states to themselves and to others? How do these=20
    >abilities develop? He reviews the main competing answers to these=20
    >questions, criticizes various forms of the theory-theory approach and=20
    >defends a version of the simulation theory approach where particular=20
    >attention is paid to introspection.
    >
    >In "How to acquire a 'representational theory of mind'," ALAN LESLIE=20
    >discusses several versions of the theory-theory of cognitive development in=
    >=20
    >its application to the acquisition a representational theory-of-mind.=20
    >Theory-theories associate the possession of a concept, in particular the=20
    >concept of belief, to some descriptive knowledge of the referents, in this=
    >=20
    >case, of beliefs. Leslie argues against this view and for a "conceptual=20
    >psycho-physical" approach where a concept such as that of belief might be=20
    >causally correlated with, or "locked to," beliefs in the world, and be that=
    >=20
    >concept just because of this locking mechanism. The concept of belief,=20
    >then, is not acquired as part of a proper 'theory' of mind. Rather the=20
    >acquisition of a theory is made possible by the possession and deployment=20
    >of the previously available concept. What makes this concept of belief=20
    >available - as well as the basic metarepresentational abilities where it=20
    >gets deployed -may well be an innate disposition rather than a learning=20
    >process.
    >
    >In "Metarepresentation and Conceptual Change: Evidence from Williams=20
    >Syndrome," SUSAN CAREY AND SUSAN JOHNSON present a case study of abnormal=20
    >cognitive development, specifically, the acquisition of a intuitive but=20
    >non-core theory of biology, by a population of retarded people with=20
    >Williams Syndrome. They argue that the bootstrapping devices that underlie=
    >=20
    >conceptual change require metarepresentational cognitive architecture.=20
    >Metarepresentational capacities that are part of the theory-of-mind module=
    >=20
    >support for instance noticing of contradictions and distinguishing=20
    >appearance from reality, thus permitting conceptual change. However, in=20
    >the case of retarded individuals, the lack of sufficient computational=20
    >capacity serves as a bottleneck, both in the construction of metaconceptual=
    >=20
    >knowledge that goes beyond the core, and in the construction of the first=20
    >theories that likewise transcend the core. This study also throws light on=
    >=20
    >the status of the 4-year-old's theory-of-mind as core knowledge or=20
    >constructed knowledge.
    >
    >DAVID ROSENTHAL's HOT (i.e. higher-order thought) theory of consciousness=20
    >is a particularly clear and crisp case of metarepresentational thinking. In=
    >=20
    >"Consciousness and Metacognition,", he defends this theory and discusses=20
    >relevant evidence from current research on metacognition and in particular=
    >=20
    >on feeling-of-knowing experiences. He argues that this evidence sheds light=
    >=20
    >on what it is to be conscious of a mental state and on what it is,=20
    >therefore, for a mental state to be conscious. He discusses important=20
    >issues having to do with the development of metacognitive abilities and=20
    >with their fallibility.
    >
    >PART III: Metarepresentations, language, and meaning
    >
    >In "Meaning, exemplarization and metarepresentation", KEITH LEHRER argues=20
    >that the human mind is essentially a "metamind" (see Lehrer 1990),=20
    >involving first level representational states that are metarepresented and=
    >=20
    >evaluated at a metalevel thus becoming states of the metamind. This permits=
    >=20
    >mental plasticity and the resolution of conflicts that at the lower level=20
    >that are unavoidable for a complex representational system. Such a=20
    >metarepresentational view seems, however, threatened by a regress (as=20
    >suggested by Wilfrid Sellars) or by circularity (as suggested by Jerry=20
    >Fodor) in accounting for language learning. Drawing on Sellars theory of=20
    >meaning, and on Nelson Goodman notion of exemplarization, Lehrer argues=20
    >that the problem of understanding meaning and of achieving representational=
    >=20
    >transparency is resolved through a harmless referential loop of ascent to=20
    >quotation and desent to disquotation.
    >
    >In "The iconicity of metarepresentations," FRAN=C7OIS RECANATI develops an=
    >=20
    >extensive and original formal treatment of the semantics of=20
    >metarepresentations. He discusses the relevant philosophical literature on=
    >=20
    >quotations and indirect reports of speech or thought, and argues, against=20
    >standard views, for a Principle of Iconicity according to which true=20
    >metarepresentations essentially resemble the representations they are=20
    >about. They are fundamentally "transparent," in that they represent what=20
    >the metarepresented representation represents and not just, "opaquely" that=
    >=20
    >representation itself. He contrast his approach to the simulation view of=20
    >metarepresentations, and speculates about the relationship between=20
    >conditionals and metarepresentations.
    >
    >In a series of influential papers, Tyler Burge has argued for the view that=
    >=20
    >the intentional states of a subject are in part determined by the social=20
    >practices of the members of his community. The disposition to defer to=20
    >experts plays an important role in this externalist view. In "Social=20
    >externalism and deference," STEVEN DAVIS discusses and refines Burge's=20
    >account. He argues that a conditional disposition to defer is essential to=
    >=20
    >concept possession. He analyzes this disposition to defer as involving=20
    >epistemic norms and a metarepresentational ability. This chapter thus=20
    >relates the metarepresentational framework to some of the most interesting=
    >=20
    >recent developments in the philosophy of language and mind.
    >
    >In "Metarepresentations in staged communicative acts," RAYMOND GIBBS=20
    >demonstrates, with linguistic and experimental evidence, how=20
    >speaker's/listener's recognition of specific metarepresentations affects=20
    >their joint production and understanding of nonserious speech, and in=20
    >particular or irony. The evidence tends to show that irony, because of its=
    >=20
    >complex metarepresentational character, requires more processing effort to=
    >=20
    >understand than tropes like metaphor. Gibbs concludes that the most general=
    >=20
    >challenge that studying metarepresentations in language poses is=20
    >to recognize how the coordination of mutual beliefs in ordinary speech=20
    >reflects essential connections between the ways people think and the ways=20
    >they produce and understand language.
    >
    >In "Metarepresentation in linguistic communication," DEIRDRE WILSON=20
    >examines the different types of metarepresentational ability involved in=20
    >linguistic comprehension. She discusses Grice's metarepresentational view=20
    >of speaker's meaning and of comprehension processes. Focusing on the use of=
    >=20
    >utterances to represent attributed utterances and thoughts, she surveys a=20
    >range of linguistic metarepresentational devices, and argues that their=20
    >analysis can both benefit from and provide useful evidence for the study of=
    >=20
    >more general metarepresentational abilities. From a historical point of=20
    >view, current approaches to metarepresentations derive from semiotic and=20
    >philosophical interest in metalinguistic devices. Deirdre Wilson's chapter,=
    >=20
    >showing how this traditional interest is now being reframed in a cognitive=
    >=20
    >perspective, provides a fitting conclusion for the whole volume.
    >
    >-----------------------------
    >Dan Sperber
    >Directeur de Recherche au CNRS (Paris)
    >
    >email: dan@sperber.com
    >web page: http://www.dan.sperber.com
    >-----------------------------
    >
    >
    >

    -------------------------------------------------
    Robyn Carston
    Department of Phonetics & Linguistics, UCL
    Gower Street, London WC1E 6BT, UK
    Tel 020 7679 3174
    Fax 020 7383 4108
    URL http://www.phon.ucl.ac.uk/home/robyn/home.htm
    -------------------------------------------------



    This archive was generated by hypermail 2b29 : Mon Aug 28 2000 - 16:35:53 GMT